Written by
Steve Knight and first published at Marx
& Philosophy Review of Books
In the 135
years since his passing, many commentators on Marx’s work have maintained that
his view of humanity’s relationship to the Earth is “Promethean,” i.e. that
mastery over nature is a key step to achieving the communist state. A
counter-tendency in Marxian analysis, however, led first in the 1960s and 70s
by scholars like Raymond Williams and Istvan Meszaros, then in the past twenty
years by a new generation including John Bellamy Foster and Paul Burkett, has
maintained that ecology’s conflict with capitalist relations is central to
understanding Marx’s political economy.
Kohei Saito,
author of Karl Marx’s Ecosocialism, belongs firmly in the latter camp. For
Saito, associate professor at Osaka City University, Marx is not simply an
economist who sometimes refers to nature; he insists that “it is not possible
to comprehend the full scope of his critique of political economy if one
ignores its ecological dimension…Marx actually deals with the whole of nature,
the ‘material’ world, as a place of resistance against capital, where the
contradictions of capitalism are manifested most clearly.”
Drawing
extensively upon Marx’s “excerpt notebooks” that have been published as part of
the ongoing research project Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe (aka MEGA), the author
paints a compelling portrait of Marx first as a young man with a philosophical
conviction of how capitalist relations alienate us from nature, then as a
determined student of natural sciences, eager to find scientific verification
of the ecological contradictions of capital.
In Part One,
“Ecology and Economy,” Saito traces the systematic development of Marx’s
ecological critique from the Paris Notebooks of the 1840s through the mature
work of Capital. Marx’s Paris work (a portion of which was published in the
twentieth century with the title Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts) shows
a young scholar still under the philosophical influence of Feuerbach and the
Young Hegelian school. He develops his fourfold definition of alienation under
capitalist relations: within capitalism, Marx claims, one becomes alienated
from the product of the one’s labor, from the labor process itself, from one’s
free and creative “species-being,” and from one’s fellow workers.
Marx proposes
overcoming these forms of alienation through the abolition of private property
(the product of alienated labor), so that humans can relate to nature in a
free, cooperative manner. While he arrived at valuable insights in this period
that laid the groundwork for later ecological thinking, Marx at this point was
still enamored of an ahistorical, Feuerbachian idealism that he would need to
transcend in order to make way for the “scientific socialism” informing his
later work.
The turning
point in Marx’s materialist critique came with The German Ideology (1846),
manuscripts he co-wrote with Friedrich Engels. Here Marx shifts from a purely
philosophical approach to ecology, into a “natural scientific” one based on a
historical understanding of evolving relations between humans and nature. He
begins using the term “metabolism”—a concept first used in the nineteenth century
by physiologists, later by philosophers—to describe this dynamic interchange,
where nature becomes man’s “inorganic body” upon which he depends for survival.
Over the next
decade, culminating in his writing of the Grundrisse in the mid-1850s, Marx
refined his understanding of the concept to posit a general metabolic tendency
of capital: in aiming for continuous expansion, capitalism exploits natural
forces--including human labor power--in search of cheaper inputs; but this
process deepens capitalism’s own contradictions (deforestation, carbon
emissions, biodiversity loss, etc.), all of which have intensified since the
time of Marx’s writing. Human civilization will likely become impossible long
before capital accumulation ceases due to ecological degradation; therefore,
capitalism’s metabolic relations are incompatible with sustainable human
development.
Saito’s
analysis is also valuable for the emphasis it gives to the concept of
“reification” as a keystone of Marx’s ecosocialism. While reification perhaps
receives its fullest expression in the chapters on “The Working Day” and
“Machinery and Large-Scale Industry” in Volume 1 of Capital, Marx developed it
gradually as part of his ecological critique. In brief, reification refers to
the process whereby private producers exchange commodities whose value is
determined as the sum total of abstract labor used in their production.
Nature’s
materials are molded into economic forms, and those forms become ossified into
“things,” but these material things can never be fully subsumed under capital.
Thus, capital threatens the continuity of man’s metabolism with nature, by
reorganizing nature to extract the maximum amount of abstract labor;
reification insures that society can be produced—and reproduced—only through the
mediation of value. Saito clarifies the point nicely: Marx does not
simply claim that humanity destroys the environment.
Rather, his ‘materialist
method’ investigates how the reified movement of capital reorganizes the trans-historical
metabolism between humans and nature and negates the fundamental material
condition for sustainable human development. Accordingly, Marx’s socialist
project demands the rehabilitation of the humans-nature relationship through
the restriction and finally the transcendence of the alien force of
reification.
In Part II,
“Marx’s Ecology and the Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe,” Saito scrutinizes newly
available material from Marx’s natural science notebooks, showing the many
writers Marx studied carefully for years to refine his ecological critique of
capital. Saito concedes that there is some evidence that Marx’s earlier
thinking about nature was “productivist,” i.e., he was optimistic that
scientific and technological advances could overcome nature’s limits.
His excerpts
from the earlier editions of Justus von Liebig’s Agricultural Chemistry and
James F.W. Johnston’s Notes on North America, both published in the 1850s,
strike a hopeful note that David Ricardo’s law of diminishing agricultural
returns could be overcome through improved soil science and land management.
Liebig’s earlier work assumed that productivity could be improved through the
use of synthetic fertilizers (a convenient position, perhaps, for an agronomist
with a sideline capitalist business as a manufacturer of chemical fertilizer!).
The turning
point for both Liebig and Marx, however, was the publication of the seventh
edition of Agricultural Chemistry in 1862, where Liebig adopted a darker theory
of “robbery agriculture” under capitalist relations. Liebig now posited a “law
of replenishment,” in which soil needs a mixture of organic and inorganic
elements to maintain productivity. While organic elements can be replenished
continuously through the atmosphere and rainfall, the loss of inorganic
(“mineral”) elements must be minimized as they are much harder to replace under
the pressure of capitalist production. Reading Liebig’s seventh edition
“deepened his [Marx’s] insight that nature cannot be arbitrarily subordinated
and manipulated through technological development.
There are insurmountable
natural limits. Marx’s demand for the rational regulation of human-nature
metabolism sprang from the recognition of natural limits, as well as that
social production must be radically reorganized to achieve sustainable human
development. Capitalism, Marx realized, is inherently inimical to this more
rational metabolism, as it mediates all relations through reified values.
Liebig’s idea
of robbery agriculture became one source of inspiration for Marx’s theory of a
“metabolic rift” between town and country in the first volume of Capital
(discussed at some length by John Bellamy Foster in his book Marx’s Ecology).
But Saito’s access to the MEGA notebooks reveals that following the publication
of Capital in 1867, Marx began reading another agronomist, Carl Fraas, whose
work—especially his 1866 book Agrarian Crises and Their
Remedies—both modified his previously unqualified praise of Liebig, and opened
a new scientific window for understanding capitalism’s ecological contradictions.
Fraas espoused an “agricultural physics” counterpoised to Liebig’s
“agricultural chemistry”; while he did not discount the importance of much of
Liebig’s work, he believed that climatic factors were of more importance than
chemical ones to soil productivity. Fraas writes at one point that cultivation
can take place without exhaustion in a favorable climate even if nutrients are
not returned to the soil in a metabolic cycle by humans.
Fraas also
maintained—particularly in another of his studies, Climate and the Plant World
Over Time—that deforestation was the primary driver of climate change, as it
inevitably led to rising temperatures and lower humidity (i.e.,
desertification), tracing this as an historical tendency in the civilizations
of Mesopotamia, Egypt and Greece.
The problem,
according to Fraas, is that civilization consumes an enormous amount of wood in
activities like building ships and houses, as well as producing iron and sugar;
therefore replanting deforested land is often not feasible. Saito observes that
“Marx, reading Fraas’s work, rightly thinks it necessary to study much more
thoroughly the negative aspect of the development of productive forces and
technology and their disruption of natural metabolism with regard to other
factors of production.”
Much work
remains for future scholars to plumb the development of Marx’s ecosocialism. As
Saito points out, the MEGA project has to date published Marx’s excerpt
notebooks only up to 1868; notebooks that track his developing ecological awareness
over his final fifteen years await full publication of the fourth section of
the MEGA. Nevertheless, “Karl Marx’s Ecosocialism” is an indispensable addition
to the burgeoning literature on Marxian ecosocialism.
Kohei Saito provides an intellectually rigorous,
yet accessible, guide for readers not only as to why healing capital’s
ecological rifts was essential to Marx’s socialist project, but also how Marx’s
decades-long reading project in the natural sciences informed his analysis from
The German Ideology onwards. “Marx did not answer all of the questions and did
not predict today’s world,”
Saito writes in his conclusion, “but it is does not
follow that his ecology is of no use today. It is undeniable that his critique
of capitalism provides an extremely helpful theoretical foundation for further
critical investigation of the current ecological crisis, and that with regard
to ecology Marx’s notebooks can prove their great importance.” Ecosocialists
everywhere should appreciate Saito’s meticulous elucidation of Marx’s evolving
understanding of capital’s incompatibility with the earth.
Indeed. This is precisely what is missing in our challenge to the malthusian ecology wing of the party and elsewhere in the " green" movement. Theory.
ReplyDeleteThanks for your comment, Nicole. If you fancy writing for the blog, please let me know.
ReplyDeleteprof premraj pushpakaran writes -- 2018 marks the 200th birth year of Karl Heinrich Marx!!!
ReplyDelete