Written by Giorgos Kallis and first published at Uneven Earth
What
we dream about the future affects how we act today. If utopias express our
desires, dystopias distill our fears. Utopias and dystopias are images we
invoke to think and act in the present, producing futures that often look very
different from either our dreams or our nightmares.
An
oft-repeated criticism against the green movement is that it is dystopian and
catastrophist (some call this ‘Malthusian’) when it comes to its diagnosis, and
utopian when it comes to its prognosis. On the one hand, greens warn of a scary
future of planetary disaster, and on the other, offer a peaceful dreamland
where people bike to their artisanal work and live in picturesque houses with
well manicured food gardens and small windmills.
Nowhere to see is a realistic
political plan on how we could ever escape from the current capitalist
nightmare, and move to something remotely close to an egalitarian and
ecological future.
I
won’t deny that some green writings, especially in the 1970s and 80s (but also
still today) merit this critique. But in the meantime, there has been a lot of
new thought, under the labels of ecosocialism, degrowth, or environmental
justice that cannot be caricatured and packaged in this simplistic mold.
And
yet this is what geographer Matt Huber does in a recent article published at
the Socialist Forum, entitled Ecosocialism: Dystopian and Scientific. Huber argues that there
are two types of green socialism, one that is utopian and unscientific, and one
that is realistic and scientific, his.
Tired dichotomies
Democratic
socialism is a project in the making, and it is important to avoid tired
dichotomies and divisions of the past, especially between green and
not-so-green socialists. I find a lot to agree with in Huber’s socialist climate politics and would fully sign on to
his concluding agenda in the Socialist Forum piece, where he defends an
‘inspiring and positive political program that can win the masses of the
working classes … built on the decommodification and universal access to
[their] needs, but also a more radical and democratic vision of organizing
production to integrate ecological knowledge’ based on ‘public transport, green
public housing … and public ownership of energy’.
Yet, before that Huber argues
that ‘degrowth oriented ecosocialists’ (his term), like us are too utopian, and
not scientific. And here I disagree.
What
I want to argue is that, first, being utopian is not a problem as Huber makes
it seem it is, and second, we are scientific, at least as scientific as Huber
can claim his position is.
Dialectical utopias
To
begin with: what does Huber mean by ‘utopian’ and ‘scientific’?
By
utopia, Huber, following Engels, understands a social arrangement that does not
and cannot exist (a place that has no place, a u-topos). If such an arrangement
cannot exist, then it is a waste and misdirection of our energies, Huber
implies.
Forgive
me the heresy, but thinking about utopias has progressed – fortunately – a lot
since Engels’ time. David Harvey, who Huber certainly reads, wrote a wonderful
book on cities and utopias almost 20 years ago (Spaces of Hope).
Harvey says we should
oppose utopias that are meant as models or blueprints – not so much because
they are unrealistic, but because the realization of a perfect ideal tolerates
no objection and crushes everything that stands in its way. Harvey recognizes,
however, the value of ‘dialectical utopias’ – contradictory and incomplete
images that express desires about the future, that challenge and make us
reflect, that generate conflict with prevalent visions and open up new
syntheses.
Ernst
Bloch famously called utopias the education of desire. As Hug March and I argued, the future prefigured in
the degrowth literature is indeed a dialectical utopia that wants to reshape
desires. When French activists and
intellectuals launched the word ‘degrowth’ in the early 90s, they intentionally
meant it as a missile slogan that would generate a conflictual antithesis to
the prevalent, and taken for granted, imaginary of growth-based development.
The hope was – and is – that this conflict would catalyze a new synthesis –
maybe not the bio-region of low-tech eco-communes utopia that Huber sees in
degrowth writings, but at least some unpredictable new future other than one
which would look exactly like capitalism, only with the workers in command.
Unscientific socialism?
Huber
claims this vision is ‘unscientific’. A scientific socialism, Huber tells us,
is one ‘grounded in analysis of what kind of socialist society is possible
given historical and material conditions’. So far so good. Only one problem:
who is to judge what is really ‘possible’?
Huber,
for example, seems to think that something close to the energy or material
consumption of an average American, secured for everyone in the world, is
possible (Huber is against wasteful capitalism, and implies that unnecessary
production and consumption could be curtailed, but is not clear what he
classifies as waste –and in any case, insists on the point of ‘abundant
energy’, which one can only think means at least as much energy as it is
currently consumed, if not more).
Energy should come from renewable energy, or
why not 80% renewable and 20% nuclear, which is fine, Huber claims – and food
from robotic agriculture. Moreover, we will do all this without exploiting
anyone, taking everyone’s concerns democratically into account, somehow
minimizing damage, or at least making those on the receiving side of such
damage concede to it ‘democratically’.
I
am a scientist too, and I think this vision is unrealistic. To use Huber’s
terms, it is ‘materially impossible’. I explain why here or here in more detail. The
emissions, land use and material extraction involved in a scenario like Huber’s
make impossible a sort of American standard of energy abundance available for
everyone (or more precisely, it can be possible but just for a few at the
expense of many others, as it has been actually till now).
And
if we were to take really into account everyone’s concerns (those who live next
to mines where the lithium for the batteries and the uranium for the reactors
will come from, those who will have to be relocated or see their landscape
destroyed to put windmills, etc) and actually compensate them for the damages
our consumption causes, then production would be inevitably much, much lower
than it is today on average. (Not to mention how much the economy would slow
down if we were to devote time to reach decisions on such matters truly
democratically).
The past is not proof of the future
Granted,
I might be wrong, and Huber right. But who is to judge whose science about what
is possible is right and whose is wrong? And what makes Huber so sure that he
is right and scientific while others are not? Any science—scientific socialism
including—is bound to be incomplete, uncertain and debatable. There are
different, contested views, of what is possible – crucially, these views cannot
be separated easily from our desires about the future.
Huber,
for example, thinks it is undesirable to live with less energy. His argument is
that since agricultural work is drudgery and no one wants to do it, societies
without fossil fuels to power tractors had to and will have to have slaves.
First, it is questionable whether the historical and anthropological record
supports the claim that all societies without fossil fuels were slave-based.
Second,
even if many were, this does not mean that we cannot have a future society
without fossil fuels, with more manual work and without slaves. The fact that
something did not exist in the past is not proof that it cannot happen in the
future – if it were, then we wouldn’t be discussing socialism to begin with.
Third,
no one that I know in the ecosocialist, degrowth or other environmentalist
communities that Huber seems to have in mind has argued for a total
substitution of fossil fuels by manual labour. It doesn’t help to take the arguments of others to their
extremes just to prove that they are impossible and unscientific. The claim of
those who support decentralized renewables or peasant agro-ecology for example
is much more nuanced and is based on the recognition that a sustainable future
would involve both cleaner energy and less energy use, as well as less use of
chemicals in agriculture.
Agro-ecological, lower-intensity models that would
involve more human labour than is currently the case in countries such as the
U.S., are advocated. But these arrangements are generally envisioned as a mix
of old and new, peasant and industrial experiences, not a total overhaul of
modern techniques or a return to a pre-capitalist mode of living.
Engels
was right and it turned out materially possible for capitalism to produce
plenty of goods at a fraction of the time they needed before. But that doesn’t
mean that it is today possible to power ever-growing energy use with renewable
and nuclear energy, with no harm done to others (or with harm done at levels
that can be ‘democratically’ tolerated by others).
These are different times
and different arguments, and the fact that siding with a ‘pro-technology’ (so
to speak) argument at one moment in time may have proved right, does not make
all similar arguments always and everywhere right or ‘scientific’.
Degrowth: radical abundance
Capitalism
produced (more than) enough, quite soon after Engels’s time, but there is still
poverty amidst an overabundance of goods and productive possibilities. This
should make us pause for a moment. The problem may not be that we are not
producing enough, but as Marx and Engels were among the first to note, that we
are not distributing equally what we are producing.
As
Jason Hickel argues in ‘Degrowth. A call for radical abundance’, the continued enclosures
and dispossessions that sustained capitalism have always been justified in the
name of growth. The story we are constantly being told is, as Malthus first put
it, in the service of his argument in defense of capitalist growth (yes,
Malthus was a defender of growth, not of limits to growth),
is that ‘there is not enough for everyone to have a decent share’.
The
artificial scarcity created in turn by enclosures makes everyone live in need,
and therefore work harder to stay afloat, which is essential if the engine is
to keep going and growing. So the problem isn’t that we don’t produce enough,
but that we can’t share the abundance that we already have.
Huber’s
vision of sharing and public luxury is not as far as he thinks from a degrowth
vision. I would only add that this has to take place in a context of private
sobriety – a sobriety that actually socialist revolutionaries of all times have
espoused and lived in their everyday lives. It is what Enrico Berlinguer,
leader of the Italian Euro-communists called ‘revolutionary austerity’. It is
the sort of personal austerity that real revolutionaries of all times have
practiced in their personal lives.
Relative versus absolute scarcity
Defending
Berlinguer’s revolutionary austerity does not make one accomplice to
Thatcherite austerity. On the contrary, what is Thatcherite is the liberal
assumption of a God-given right of each and everyone to mobilize all resources
possible in their pursuit of their individual (or collective) goals.
According
to this ingrained liberal view, we cannot tell people that we could perhaps
live better with less, because it is people’s god given right to want more and
more, as much as those richer have. What is more revolutionary instead than
Gandhi’s plea to ‘live simply so that others may simply live’?
Huber
agrees that there is so much waste going on within capitalism, and so much work
expended just to goods and services whose purpose is no other than to pay for
rents and profits. Then just ending profits and rents could reduce resource use
significantly. Why insist on robots and nuclear plants if we could live with
less and sustain a decent material standard of living for everyone?
Note
also that what counts as ‘decent’ living is always socially determined and it
makes little sense to defend an average, or middle class standard of living. A
poor person today does not die from diseases that royals died in bygone eras.
But if your loved one dies from a curable disease that a rich person can pay to
treat, this creates a real sense of scarcity.
Crucially,
this scarcity is relative. If housing was public and cheap, Hickel argues, then people could live
with well with a fraction of their salary – and produce and consume much less
than they do now. To imagine an absolute scarcity, and use it as a
justification for mobilizing ever more work and ever more resources in the name
of making everyone have what the rich persons of their epoch happen to have, is
a fundamental myth that sustains capitalism.
Bending
material reality is not scientific
Huber
also has a second take on the meaning of ‘scientific’. He writes that ‘let’s
get real, or ‘scientific’ … we are not going to win the masses of workers with
a socialist program based on … ‘drudgery for all’. Science here seems to refer
to realism about how can ‘we’ (sic) win the masses of workers. There are
problems with this formulation too.
First,
even if Huber were right and there were a mass of workers that wouldn’t be
mobilized to anything that sounds like ‘less’, that still wouldn’t make it
materially possible to have ever more stuff. Huber argues that given that the
workers will never buy into a degrowth utopia then ‘the key to an ecosocialist
future is finding some way to replicate the labor-saving aspects of the fossil
economy with clean energy’.
This
actually seems to me a very unscientific, and utopian in the bad sense – having
to ‘find some way’ to make something possible, independently of whether it is
materially possible or not. Rather than consider integrating your political
strategy to what is materially possible, the call here is to bend material
possibility, one way or the other, to what you came to think as the only
possible political strategy.
Fixed desires
But,
second, like the statement on material possibility, the idea that some of us
can know with certainty the limits of political possibility – that is, know
what the workers really want – is also problematic. Who is to say that workers
everywhere and always would only be attracted to visions of ‘more’?
I
live in Barcelona, and our mayor Ada Colau won the municipal elections with the
support of a substantial fraction of the working class. Her program emphasized
dignity and equality, not growth and material affluence. Colau wanted to stop
evictions and secure decent housing for everyone, she did not have to promise
air-conditions and cheap charter flights for all (I am not saying that Huber
advocates these, but Leigh Phillips, a provocateur who Huber for some reason
enthusiastically cites twice, does).
Third,
Huber implicitly assumes that what workers want is fixed, and that desires
cannot be shaped through reflection and dialogue. This leaves no space for new
ideas or new desires and makes one wonder, how is it that workers come to want
what they want, and how does this ever change in time? If we follow Huber’s
logic then we can only cater to what exists, never shape the possible – this to
me seems a quite restricted view of the political.
Politics
has a make-believe quality. Pre-defining what is possible leads to self-fulfilled
prophecies. If we assume that we cannot even utter our dreams of a different
future, because they are unrealistic and impossible, then of course ‘workers’
will want what they currently want and alternative dreams will remain
unrealistic and impossible.
But
fourth, and more importantly, it is not clear why, for Huber, ‘we’ who write
these things are not part of the working class, and can’t understand what
‘they’ want. If the working class is those who have to sell their labour in
order to survive, then it is not only coal miners and Joe the plumbers that
make the working class, not even only nurses and teachers, but also we
University professors and the precarious post-docs and students that read our
musings.
Those among us who desire some sort of a degrowth future are not some
weird romantic animals, different from the rest of working people – we are not
people who live from rents, we are workers like anyone else who have to work in
order to make it from month to month.
Of
course there are different experiences, and different power positions within a
broadly defined working class, or the 99%. We shouldn’t be blind to our
positionalities, for example, as academic urbanites, with a decent income, a
health insurance, flying regularly and so on. But the desires of education
workers or precarious youngsters are as legitimate as those of factory workers.
And our desires do not necessarily have to be different either (actually
keeping them different is essential for the hegemony of capitalism). And they
are increasingly not different, as the incomes, social protections and
privileges of the professional middle income groups are collapsing.
Chris
Carlsson and Fransesca Manning write about a new ‘nowtopian‘
experience of class, shared among parts of the precariat which finds work and
meaning outside wage labour, in urban gardens, social centres or pirate
programming. Nowtopians formed the backbone of the occupied squares. Waving
away dreams like theirs as unscientific (and implicitly, elitist) is not doing
the building of a broad movement any service.
Reducing complex debate into outdated
binaries
In
conclusion, both material and social conditions are much more complex and
uncertain than Huber allows for. Huber, I am afraid, is reducing a complex
debate into simple binaries of the sort ‘(post)-industrial future’ versus ‘back
to slavery’ (if not back to the caves).
The
choices ahead are much more nuanced than that and will involve different
hybrids of advanced and simplified techniques and modes of living. Consumption
will have to go down and production will need to be cleaner – fortunately this
can be experienced as an improvement in living if the commons are reclaimed and
shared equally.
The discourses and visions that will mobilize the 99% to an
eco-socialist future are bound to be context-specific, but I firmly believe
they can be constructed in a Colau-style fashion around ideas of sufficiency
and sharing the commons equally, while securing a dignified life for all.
If
something disappoints me, and motivated me to write this essay, it is the
feeling that no matter how hard some of us work to advance and refine a certain
strain of green-left thought (call it degrowth, ecosocialism or else), we are
bound to be caricatured as a blend of socialist utopians of the 19th century
and neo-Malthusians of the 1970s (never mind the stark differences between
these two sets of ideas).
We
owe ourselves and the few people who might read us a more informed and refined
debate than a repetition of tired dichotomies from the 1970s. Reality is
complex, what is possible and what not is hard to know, and the roads to
ecosocialism (or however else you might want to call an egalitarian and sustainable
future) are many.
Aaron
Vansintjan commented on a previous draft and helped me improve this text.
Giorgos
Kallis is an ICREA professor of political ecology and ecological economics at
ICTA-UAB in Barcelona. He is the author of Degrowth (2018, Agenda Publishing).
A collection of his essays and media articles, ‘In Defense of Degrowth,’ can be
downloaded free of cost.
No comments:
Post a Comment