The Return
of Nature is a
genealogy of ecological thinking. The word ‘ecology’ was not in common usage
until the twentieth century, leading many to consider ecological thinking a
fairly recent development. However, in this impressive volume, John Bellamy
Foster convincingly identifies a materialist ecological sensibility within
works dating back a century prior to ecology’s popularization.
Starting with
the funerals of Darwin and Marx in 1882 and 1883 respectively, the book traces
how socialist thinkers in the nineteenth and early twentieth century were
integral to developing an outlook that acknowledges the complex relationship
between human production and the rest of nature.
The scientific
discipline of ecology is sometimes assumed to have developed from a series of
scientific studies, free from social and political influences. By the same
logic, some also suppose that the socialist thinkers of the nineteenth century
had little interest in ecological concerns, and consequently that the left were
latecomers to the environmental movement in the late twentieth century.
Foster’s work, both here and in his earlier
books, has been driven by a desire to counter these views and therefore
demonstrate the importance of Marxism for today’s radical
ecological movements. His aim is to show that Marx adopted an ecological
worldview throughout his writings; Marx saw humans as part of nature but also
able to actively relate to nature through their labor.
The Return
of Nature was
published at the start of the COVID-19 pandemic (which is briefly mentioned in
the prologue), yet much of the discussion is relevant to how we might analyze
its origins and effects. Victorian cities such as London suffered terrifying
epidemics of diseases including typhoid, typhus and cholera. As with COVID-19
today, these disproportionately affected the poorest residents with the worst
living conditions. This is something Marx was also familiar with, especially as
the Marx family was living in Soho in central London during a particularly
deadly cholera outbreak in 1854.
The story of
how the source of the cholera epidemic was identified is well known. The
physician John Snow convinced the authorities that cholera was a waterborne
disease, rather than one spread through the air, and located the source at a
water pump on Broad Street. When the handle of the water pump was removed such
that people couldn’t drink the water, the epidemic subsided.
Less well known
is the mutual influence of science and socialism among some of the other
protagonists of the story. After the epidemic, further investigations carried
out by Edwin Lankester found that the well feeding the Broad Street pump was
contaminated by a cesspit at 40 Broad Street, the site of one of the first
cases of cholera. Lankester was part of a struggle against the conditions in
which nineteenth century workers lived and worked, including crowded homes,
overwork, and poor sanitation.
In the
discussion of Victorian working conditions, Marx, in Volume 1 of Capital,
cites Lankester’s investigation into the case of a dressmaker named Mary Ann
Walkley, who died after being made to work more than twenty-six hours without a
break.
Although not a
revolutionary, Lankester had radical views and talked about being on the side
of the masses. His son, E. Ray Lankester, was a similarly impressive figure, a
member of the Royal Society who directed the Natural History Museum in London
between 1898 and 1907 — although he was apparently dismissed from this role for
his attacks on the museum establishment. The younger Lankester was also a close
associate of Marx and one of the few people to attend his funeral.
Stephen Jay
Gould, in “The Darwinian Gentleman at Marx’s Funeral,” referred to him as “a
basically conservative biologist” and suggested that he saw in Marx’s
friendship little more than an opportunity to discuss art and philosophy with
another brilliant intellectual. However, Foster has a different take on their
relationship. He accepts that Lankester did have some conservative views in
later life. Depressingly, he did oppose women’s suffrage on the basis that he
thought women did not have the same intellectual abilities as men.
But Foster also
highlights Lankester’s critique of the way in which a capitalist system driven
by the needs of the market would have dangerous ecological consequences,
including the spread of new disease epidemics and the increasing extinction of
species. Lankester once wrote that “the capitalist wants cheap labour, and he
would rather see the English people poor and ready to do his work for him, than
better off.”
Foster also
makes much of Lankester’s views on degeneration. In essence, Lankester was
critical of the assumption that biological evolution was a story of continual
progress towards more complex forms and argued that it could also result in
less complex organisms. This form of what he called “degeneration” could be
said to apply to human civilizations when humans undermine the ecological
conditions of their own existence.
So for
Lankester, human history was, like the evolution of species, not simply a case
of linear progress. Instead, he followed Marx in stressing the agency of humans
to make their own history, though not under conditions of their choosing.
Seeing the association between Marx and Lankester as a mere curiosity overlooks
the radical implications of some of Lankester’s views as well as Marx’s own
deep interest in Darwin and evolution.
According to
Foster, there are two lines of influence that can be detected by examining the
thought of ecological socialist thinkers. One goes from Marx to Lankester and
subsequently to figures such as ecologist Arthur Tansley and H. G. Wells, a
Fabian socialist as well as an author. The other line runs from Engels via the
1930s generation of “red scientists” and into the late twentieth
century.
Engels was
indeed one of the most important Marxist figures in the development of an
ecological materialist worldview; a substantial portion of this book is devoted
to “Engels’s Ecology.” Engels set out to produce an account of how the
dialectical processes Marx had uncovered in his study of society could also be
observed by studying nature.
As Foster
explains, dialectics takes “as its fundamental reality the ever-changing
character — as well as resulting contradictions, negations, and qualitative
transformations — of both the material world at large and the human condition
within it.” It is a philosophy that sees dynamism as inherent to the way the
world works rather than assuming that things remain static unless they are
influenced by an outside force.
Engels’s notes
were published decades after his death as The Dialectics of Nature with
the help of JBS Haldane, one of the founding figures of modern evolutionary
biology and a sympathizer of the Communist Party. From the early twentieth
century, there has been a protracted debate among Marxists surrounding this
text and, more broadly, whether Engels was right or wrong to argue that
dialectical processes exist in nature — where human subjectivity does not play
a role.
This is not
helped by the fact that The Dialectics of Nature was not
published in Engels’ lifetime and the various published editions have been
translated and edited posthumously by others. Therefore, it is difficult to
know what a final text from Engels would have looked like or whether he would
have expressed his ideas in the same way if he had been able to finish working
through his ideas.
However, this
does not mean that we cannot learn much from Engels. He developed an account of
nature that recognized that it could be understood in historical terms.
Processes of change and development, and sometimes abrupt or qualitative leaps,
are inherent to the natural world. In the nineteenth century, this would have
been demonstrated most strikingly by Darwin’s account of the evolution of new
species.
Key to Engels’s
thinking was the recognition that humans are a part of nature but are also able
consciously to manipulate the environment around them and, in the process,
change themselves. Engels’ dialectical materialism was at odds with the
prevalent mechanical materialist views of the late nineteenth century,
which tended to reduce the natural world to passive matter and treat it as
fixed rather than dynamic.
As Foster
demonstrates, if we want to address Engels’ ecological thought, we should also
turn our attention to his other works, including The Condition of the
Working Class in England, a much earlier book in which he
describes the effects of water and air pollution and disease epidemics, and
analyzes how capitalism has created the conditions for these environmental
hazards.
A later
chapter, “A Science for the People,” discusses the organization of that name in
the 1970s and 1980s (whose magazine, also called Science for the People,
was a forerunner of this publication) and the nearest thing to a British
equivalent, the British
Society for Social Responsibility in Science. Foster rightly points out
that the original Science for the People was influenced by the 1930s generation
in their critique of the idea that science is separate from social relations.
But they had
some key political differences. As part of the New Left, they were less likely
to be sympathetic to greater state control of science compared to previous
generations. Several members of the organization were associated with
developments in biological and ecological thinking. For example, Science for
the People member Richard Levins was part of developing an ecological critique
of the assumption that there is harmony in nature.
He described a
co-evolutionary relationship of humanity and nature where processes of change
are inherent to both. Foster also points to a 1973 editorial in the original magazine,
“Ecology for the People,” in which members of the organization called for
revolution as the solution to the social inequality and ecological devastation
that is typical under capitalism.
The example set
by the likes of Levins or Lankester shows how scientific enquiry has often been
influenced by the philosophical viewpoints of scientists and their concerns for
social and environmental justice. It demonstrates that we cannot treat science
as a neutral activity carried out by apolitical thinkers.
Indeed, as
Foster argues, the politics of these scientists informed their ecological
worldview and “it is this method of ecological critique arising out of the
socialist critique of capitalist society that is seen here as most important,
since it provides the indispensable means for a revolutionary dialectical
ecology.”
Most of the key
thinkers described in the book are men. However, Foster does point to some
fascinating examples of women in science going back to the nineteenth century,
whose work has not been so well known. For example, it is likely that the
biologist Phebe Lankester (the wife of Edwin) was part of the investigation of
the water from the Broad Street well. But as a woman, her work would have been
carried out “behind the scenes.” Engels’s The Condition of the Working
Class in England was first translated to English by an American woman,
Florence Kelley, in the 1880s.
Kelley was the
chief inspector of factories in Chicago, who investigated the brutal conditions
of child laborers in the city and campaigned for an 8-hour day. She played a
major role in the social history of the United States.
The Return
of Nature is
focused on Britain, with a few exceptions including the section on Science for
the People. This has allowed Foster to trace a coherent narrative, drawing out
the influence of Marx, Engels, and Darwin in the country where they spent most
of their lives.
Of course, any
project of this type is bound to be limited in the amount of ground it can
cover, but it is worth acknowledging some of the gaps as readers may want to
consider how their own research could add to our knowledge of the contributions
of women or thinkers from other parts of the world. The book also leaves open
the question of whether we are now seeing the start of a new generation of
scientific radicals in the twenty-first century.
Rather than
providing a conclusion, Foster ends the book with a short chapter on the Greek
philosopher Epicurus, the subject of Marx’s doctoral thesis. It seems that
Foster would prefer to let the thinkers whose work he discusses speak for
themselves, rather than try to provide an overall summary of their varied
thought — which would also be impossible to attempt in this short review.
Perhaps what we
can say is that one of the central contributions of dialectical thinking is its
rebuke to the assumption that “nature” is a fixed or stable realm separate from
human society. This dualistic way of thinking so often results in the
environment being treated as an afterthought in our understanding of social relations
— or worse — as an externality to the economic calculations of capitalists.
By contrast,
ecology as a scientific discipline addresses the relationships between living
things and with their abiotic surroundings. This emphasis has led some ecologists
towards an understanding of the role of human activity within such systems.
As Foster
therefore argues, the legacy of the nineteenth and twentieth century thinkers
discussed in the book is one “that we can no longer afford to do without in our
age of combined ecological and social crisis.”
The Return
of Nature shows
how — if we want to understand issues such as climate change, biodiversity
loss, or the emergence of new pandemics today — it will take thorough research
into ecological systems that also addresses the influence of human activity.
That research will be driven by a demand for transformative societal change.
We can use the
analytical tools of the thinkers presented here to start to make sense of the
destructive influence of capitalism on the biosphere and also paint a more
hopeful picture of what a more rational relationship to the rest of the natural
world might look like.
The Return
of Nature introduces
us to some of the key figures in the development of an ecological worldview.
Some of them, such as the writer and designer William Morris or biologist JBS
Haldane, are relatively famous.
Others, such as
biologist Lancelot Hogben and the extraordinary British writer Christopher
Caudwell are less widely known. Foster has shone new light on their lives and
work. The book took years to write (at over 500 pages excluding the notes,
Foster describes this as his “big book”) and involved dedicated research from
numerous archival resources.
The result is a
volume full of biographical detail as well as sketches of the key contributions
of the various thinkers to ecological thinking. Readers of Science for
the People will be rewarded with many examples of great scientific
radicals from previous generations to admire, and an opportunity to find out
more about the figures who are, in many ways, the forebears of the producers
and readers of this magazine.
Monthly Review
Press
2020
672 Pages
$28
About the
Author
Camilla
Royle teaches Geography at King’s College London and the London School of
Economics. Her PhD research addressed the ideas of Richard Levins, Richard
Lewontin, and other dialectical biologists. Her work has been published
in International Socialism, Antipode, and Human
Geography.
Editors
Erik Wallenberg
(Lead Editor)
Cliff Conner (Co-Editor)
Rebecca Roskill (Technical Editor)
Sonja Soo (Copy Editor)
Good to see this significant contribution to eco-socialism being acknowledged by Green Left. And thank you for taking on the task of reviewing such considerable undertaking by John Bellamy Foster.
ReplyDelete