Written by Gabriel Levy and first published at People and Nature
A response to
Fully Automated Luxury Communism: A Manifesto by Aaron Bastani (Verso Books,
2019)
Communist
utopias are the stuff of life. They have given hope, widened horizons and fired
imaginations, from Nikolai Chernyshevsky’s What Is To Be Done (1863) and
William Morris’s News from Nowhere (1890) through to Woman On the Edge of Time
(1985) by Marge Piercy.
So when my
copy of Aaron Bastani’s Fully Automated Luxury Communism: A Manifesto arrived,
I had high hopes. They were not all realised.
There were
things in Bastani’s book I really liked: his optimism, and his conviction that
any communist society – that is, any society free of exploitation and hierarchy
– will be based on
material abundance. But his ideas about how this might be achieved were
unconvincing.
Fully
Automated Luxury Communism (FALC), he writes in the concluding chapter, is
a map by which we escape the labyrinth
of scarcity and a society built on jobs; the platform from which we can begin
to answer the most difficult question of all, of what it means, as [the
economist John Maynard] Keynes once put it, to live ‘wisely and agreeably and
well’ (p. 243).
Bastani
writes that FALC, unlike the world of actually existing neoliberalism,
will not demand constant sacrifices on
the altar of profit and growth. Whether it’s ‘paying down the debt for future
generations’, as our politicians are so keen to repeat, or growth and rising
wages always coming ‘next year’ it’s becoming ever clearer that the good times
aren’t coming back. What remains absent, however, is a language able to
articulate that which is both accessible and emotionally resonant.
Bastani
aspires to provide that language – by identifying political principles for a
movement beyond capitalism; by returning abundance to a central place in
socialist thought; and by pointing to technological change as the basis for
social change. I will comment on these three aspects of the book in turn.
Politics and
transitions
To put
society on the road to a communist future, “a populist politics is necessary”,
Bastani writes (p. 187). A politics that
blends culture and government with
ideas of personal and social renewal. One that, to borrow a term, invents the
future.[1] Anything less will fall short.
This politics
includes elements widely shared by the left wing of social democracy (i.e.
“Corbynism” in the UK): a break with neoliberalism; “relocalisation of
economies through progressive procurement and municipal protectionism”;
“socialising finance and creating a network of local and regional [state]
banks”; and “a set of universal basic services which take much of the national
economy into public ownership” (p. 208).
On an
international level, Bastani suggests a tax of $25/tonne on carbon emissions
from high-GDP countries, to channel resources from rich countries responsible
for climate change to poorer ones (p. 222).
Where Bastani
completely loses me is with his vague suggestions about how we might move from
these social-democratic reforms of the capitalist state towards communism, and
about who might be the motive forces of such a movement.
“The return
of ‘the people’ as the main political actor is inevitable”, he writes (p. 191)
– but sees this less as the active participation of people in changing society
as an appeal (by who? politicians? activists?) to the people.
“Many”
understand that the problems are large and unprecedented, and that the solutions
must be, too, Bastani writes. So, given the possibilities afforded by
technological change, “promise them what they deserve – promise everything” (p.
192). But who is making these promises?
Not a party
based on the model of the 1917 Russian revolution, he argues. I don’t want one
of those either, but the alternative Bastani offers – a focus on electoral
politics – is equally unattractive. He writes:
The majority of people are only able
to be politically active for brief periods of time. To an extent this is
regrettable, the outgrowth of a culture that intentionally cultivates apathy
and constrains a wider sense of popular power. […] The problem is not,
therefore, that most people do not care about politics but rather they can not
afford to care [in the face of work commitments, family, and so on]. […] it is
often only around elections when large sections of society – particularly the
most exploited – are open to new possibilities regarding how society works […]
This seems to
me a dismal, conservative perspective, based on a misunderstanding of how
social change happens. The most significant political shifts of recent decades
– the fall of the Stalinist regimes in the former Soviet bloc in 1989-91, the
“Arab spring” of 2011, the Greek revolt against austerity policy imposed by the
EU – have all been initiated and carried through by mass movements on the
streets and in communities. The defeats and setbacks, most obviously in Egypt
and Syria after the revolts, do not alter that reality.
In the rich
countries too, many of the greatest changes in our lifetimes have been brought
about by movements in society – trade union movements, the women’s movement,
struggles around environmental protection – that originated outside parliament
and only found reflection there subsequently. In all these cases, people
engaged in social movements outside parliament with little regard for electoral
process.
I cannot
imagine an earth-shaking social transformation – the movement towards communism
– that does not have at its centre the active participation of millions of
people. This was a core belief of 19th century communists, and it is one we
should retain.
In the 1840s,
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels wrote about the working class doing away with
labour and doing away with the whole idea of classes and nationalities; for the
“production on a mass scale of this communist consciousness”, “a practical
movement, a revolution” is necessary; to achieve it, not only would the ruling
class have to be overthrown, but the class doing the overthrowing would have to
“rid itself of all the muck of ages and become fitted to found society
anew”.[2]
I agree with
Bastani that a “revolution” taking us towards communism can not and will not be
a re-run of Russia in 1917. It can only be something completely different. But
I can not envisage it without the active participation of millions of people.
It’s not about politicians “promising them what they deserve”. They must become
the historical subject of a process in which politics as a way of doing things
would be superceded. As Marx and Engels put it in The Communist Manifesto,
“when […] class distinctions have disappeared, and all production has been
concentrated in the hands of a vast association of the whole nation, the public
power will lose its political character.”
Obviously,
there is a long, complex discussion to be had about this. I thought Bastani
could have paid more attention to the piles of books by communist writers who
have considered this transition to communism.
Even the
utopian fiction writers imagined not only communist futures, but also the paths
by which people might get there. Think of the characters in The Dispossessed by
Ursula Le Guin, who recall the bitter struggle to establish an anarchist
commune on one of the planets depicted. When it comes to prefiguring the social
character of this transition, Bastani’s book is pretty light.
Scarcity and
abundance
The future
will be shaped by the rapid development of computers, robots and other forms of
automation, Bastani writes, which mean that there will be “extreme supply” of
both information and labour (p. 37); this abundance will form the basis for
FALC.
Capitalism,
Bastani argues, operates with “a central presumption” that “scarcity will
always exist” (p. 137). Twentieth-century “socialism”, in the Soviet Union for example,
was also based on scarcity. Now a “tendency to extreme supply” in energy,
labour and resources undermines this presumption. In the present technological
revolution, which Bastani defines as the “third disruption”,[3] “the ‘fact’ of
scarcity is moving from inevitable certainty to political imposition” (p. 243);
now, the market imposes “artificial scarcity” (pages 154-156).
We are moving
into a post-scarcity age, Bastani believes; information wants to be free;
labour wants to be free; these driving forces will not only overcome what he
calls the “five crises” of our times – climate change, resource scarcity, aging
population, a “surplus of the global poor” and the “new machine age which will
herald ever-greater technological unemployment” – but also bring the
possibility of FALC (pages 22-23).
Here, again,
Bastani loses me. I do not believe we live at a historical turning point
between past scarcity and future abundance. And I do not believe the
dividing-line between scarcity and abundance is as clear-cut as he thinks it
is.
Firstly, it
all depends on what you mean by scarcity. Radical scholars long ago took a
hammer to this concept. Nicholas Xenos showed how the emerging capitalist class
in 18th century Europe “invented scarcity”, at the same time as they
accumulated unprecedented wealth. Lyla Mehta and other researchers long ago
dissected the way that politicians, development agencies and international
financial institutions use the idea of “scarcity” to justify the imposition of
hardship and misery across the global south.[4]
So when
Bastani writes that capitalism has always been characterised by scarcity, I can
not agree. Capitalism has manufactured “scarcity” throughout its history. The
Irish potato famine of the 1840s started as a potato harvest failure that was
real enough, but was turned into a catastrophe by social structures and trade
policies. Mike Davis’s powerful, and frightful, book Late Victorian Holocausts
shows how this cruelty was reproduced across the world in the late 19th
century.
Both real
scarcity and manufactured “scarcity” are to a large degree socially
constructed; they are not caused by the lack of the right technology. There
were no natural or technological barriers to feeding the world’s population in
the twentieth century, but it was not fed. As the Indian economist Amartya Sen
showed over a life’s work, famines were caused not by shortages of food, but by
the food being in the wrong place, controlled by the wrong people, and having
its supply disrupted by wars.
Nor is it so
obvious that the 21st century will be a time of “post-scarcity”. The expansion
of the capitalist economy in its late-20th-century form produced a new set of
tensions between humanity and nature, often referred to as “planetary
boundaries”, that could also be called “scarcities”. What is the global warming
effect, the main cause of climate change, if not a “scarcity” of atmosphere
into which the economy can pour endless quantities of carbon dioxide and
methane? What is the global “fresh water crisis” if not a shortage of water
resources caused in the first place by the unplanned plunder inherent in
capitalist industry and urban infrastructure? But these “scarcities”, too, are
essentially produced by the social and economic structures in which we live:
they are not the natural or inevitable outcome of human population.
The
technological transformations of the late 19th and early 20th centuries,
including the invention of electricity, motorised transport and agricultural
fertilisers, did not – given a world economy and social structure dominated by
capitalism – prevent famine or other so-called “scarcities”. Indeed the most
cutting-edge technology was used to visit disaster on society in the form of
war. And there is plenty of evidence that the technological transformations of
our times will – again, given capitalist domination – be turned against
humanity by aggravating the climate crisis.
Technology
and society
Technological
innovation, rather than social change, is the central driving-force towards
communism, in Bastani’s view. Under capitalism, a “tendency to perpetually
innovate as a result of competition, to constantly supplant work performed by
humans and maximise productivity” has produced the “third disruption” (p. 37);
this has tended to make information the basis of value under modern capitalism;
technologies “now paradoxically tend towards destroying the scarcity of
information, and therefore its value” (p. 49); the law of “extreme supply” is
in full swing; this is the basis for “a world beyond jobs, profit and even
scarcity” (p. 49).
(Bastani
incorrectly attributes the view that “technological innovation is an inherent
feature of capitalism” to Karl Marx. Actually, Marx’s view was far more
complex: he saw in 19th century capitalism not only a tendency to push
technologies forward, but also the way in which, in capital’s hands, they
towered over humanity, feeding into the tyranny of dead labour over living
labour. I wrote about this here and here.)
Having set
out his claim that capitalist competition inevitably pushes technology forward,
Bastani gives us chapter after chapter on the progressive potential of
automation; of “post-scarcity in energy” thanks to renewables; of asteroid
mining; of gene editing to transform health care; and for synthetic food to
replace meat consumption.
Only after
this relentless hymn to technology’s virtues, in the very last chapter, does
Bastani comment that “how technology is created and used, and to whose
advantage, depends on the political, ethical and social context from which it
emerges” (p. 237). And, without considering a single example of the corrosive,
poisonous impact of 21st century capitalism on the technologies emerging within
it, cites only examples to show that technologies have “developed alongside
news ideas of nature, selfhood and forms of production”, e.g. synthetic meat
came alongside environmentalism and renewable energy alongside concern about
climate change (pages 238-239).
Once again,
Bastani has lost me.
Firstly, the
idea that the relationship between capitalism and technology can be summed up
as a “tendency to perpetually innovate as a result of competition” is a gross
over-simplification. As historians of technology have shown time and time
again, innovation is shaped – pushed forward but also constrained – not only by
competition between capitalists, but by all the other forces at work in
capitalist society.
How many
examples do you need? In medicine, the corralling of cheap and generic
treatments by multinational corporations, to make them a means for looting
state budgets rather than for healing the sick, has long been an international
scandal. In agriculture, the privileging of monocultures fed by
fossil-fuel-produced fertilisers has for decades been weaponised against
technologies that support small farmers in the global south. In the field of
energy, some crucial innovations in electricity generation from wind and solar
came in the early 20th century, others in the 1980s; in first-world electricity
markets dominated by big corporations, these technologies (together with heat and
electricity co-generation techniques) were starved of funds and stopped from
diffusing, to protect the domination of fossil fuels and the hopelessly
expensive (and ultimately not so successful) expansion of nuclear power.
I could go
on. In Bastani’s book, closer attention to such examples might have helped. But
that would have spoiled the picture he paints, of technology as a fundamentally
progressive force, nurtured by the capitalist market and requiring only
“appropriate politics” to free itself from that market. Here are three examples
of technologies where this approach leads him to absurd conclusions.
Information
technology, robotics and automation, Bastani argues, will produce
“technological unemployment”; if only neo-liberalism can be superceded by a
welfare state providing universal basic services, FALC beckons. It seems not to
have occurred to him that one of the first obstacles to be overcome in a
movement to supercede capitalism is the use of information technology by
multinational corporations and governments, to reinforce repressive social
control on one hand and the individualising logic of consumer society on the
other. (I recommend Shoshana Zuboff’s frightening and detailed discussion of
these processes in her book The Age of Surveillance Capitalism, or James
Bridle’s journalistic descriptions in The New Dark Age.)
For Bastani,
capitalism drives technology forward by the law of competition; if this can
only be suppressed, the technology will drive forward social change. So he
takes no account of the fact that social structure shapes technology and
changes the way that it develops. The transformation of the internet from the
global collective its pioneers dreamed of, to a tool for state and corporate
power, is a lesson.
With regard
to energy, Bastani focuses on the sharply falling costs of solar electricity
generation, which, he says, will make possible a transition away from fossil
fuels. The internet of things and electric cars mean that “in just a few years”
saving energy “will be entirely automated” (p. 111). Most electricity will be
produced by renewables – indeed “this is already starting to happen”, he
claims, noting that in 2016 in the UK wind farms generated more electricity
than coal for the first time (p. 112).
This very
poor passage reads like a National Grid corporate brochure. For producing
electricity in the UK, it’s true that wind is used more than coal – but it’s
also true that gas, a fossil fuel, is used far, far more than both. What’s
more, only about a quarter of all the fuels used go to producing electricity;
the rest are for transport, for industrial processes, for heating, and so on.
These are the harder bits to decarbonise, and almost no progress has been made.
As for electric cars storing energy: that will not reduce carbon emissions by
much as long as the steel for the cars is produced with coal (and that’s a
really tricky technology to change) and the electricity is produced with gas.
It is
entirely possible to move away from fossil fuels. But it will mean changing
whole technological systems, remaking urban infrastructure, confounding
consumerist culture, rethinking the way we live – and, above all, challenging
the power of oil companies, electricity companies, car manufacturers and all
the rest who dominate the current system.
For Bastani,
technological change inevitably provides an impetus to social change. I think
he’s looking at it the wrong way round. In my view, only radical social change
will make possible the technological transformations needed to move away from
fossil fuels.
Asteroid
mining is another of Bastani’s enthusiasms. Competition between technology
companies will drive down the costs of space travel, he claims, and free
humanity from shortages of the rare metals needed for computer technologies. He
doesn’t comment on the dangers that an industry controlled completely by a
handful of companies working closely with the military will move in nefarious,
even destructive, directions. Post-capitalism will be forever released from
“conditions of abiding scarcity”, he writes; “the limits of the earth won’t
matter any more – because we’ll mine the sky instead” (p. 119).
This gave me
that corporate brochure feeling again. There are any number of capitalist
adventurers out there on line, promising investors a new gold rush. But
journalists and academics who cover this stuff make clear that, if asteroid
mining has any significance in the next few decades – and it might not do – it
will be for providing tiny quantities of material from near-earth asteroids for
use in space, e.g. on long-range missions, space stations, and so on. (See a
quick, sceptical overview here or a detailed, more optimistic academic paper
here.)
Shipping substantial
quantities of metals back to earth is just not on the horizon of even the most
imaginitive researchers, given the laws of gravity, economics, and so on.
But there’s
no telling Bastani. He writes that the asteroid 16 Psyche, between Mars and Jupiter
is “the most instructive example”, which shows that “mining space would create
such outlandish supply as to collapse prices on Earth” (p. 134). And to
underline this point, he cites a figure of $10,000 quadrillion for the value of
iron on 16 Psyche. It’s a shame he didn’t also cite Lindy Elkins-Tanton, the
space researcher who came up with that number, who said: “I calculated it for
fun. […] But of course it’s an irrelevant number because (a) if you brought it
to Earth it wouldn’t be worth that any more and (b) there’s no way to bring it
to Earth. It’s a complete fantasy.”
I have no
clue whether someone will be mining asteroids in a hundred years’ time. But I
do know that, in that time frame, humanity will damn well have to have tackled
climate change, or it will have more things to worry about than ferrying rare
metals around in space. Asteroid mining will not solve the problem of mineral
resources to supply the renewable energy industry. The time scales are all
wrong. Other solutions will have to be found.
This is one
more example of the reality that Bastani avoids: that 21st century
technologies, and the ways they are used, are shaped by the relations of power
and wealth that dominate society. Without social change, these technologies
will be mobilised, now and maybe in future, for the interests of power and
wealth against humanity.
Bastani’s
one-sided view of technology, as a force that inevitably drives towards a
communist future, is far less than the forces fighting for radical social
change deserve. We can do better.
[1] Inventing the Future: postcapitalism and a world without work is the title of a book, by Alex Williams and Nick Srnicek, that Bastani cites. You can read my response to the book, prepared prior to a debate with Nick Srnicek, here
[1] Inventing the Future: postcapitalism and a world without work is the title of a book, by Alex Williams and Nick Srnicek, that Bastani cites. You can read my response to the book, prepared prior to a debate with Nick Srnicek, here
[2] This is a key passage of The German Ideology (1846), a book in which Marx and Engels worked out many of their communist ideas in detail for the first time
[3] According to Bastani, the first disruption was the start of agriculture in the Neolithic era, the second was the 18th century industrial revolution, and the third is the current technological revolution.
[4] See Nicholas Xenos, Scarcity and Modernity (Routledge, 1989), and Lyla Mehta (ed.), The Limits to Scarcity (Earthscan, 2010)
https://www.worldsocialism.org/spgb/socialist-standard/2010s/2019/no-1378-june-2019/
ReplyDelete