Written by
Michael Löwy, and first published at Capitalism Nature Socialism
ABSTRACT: The
following is a brief survey of Marx and Engels’ views on ecology, from the
viewpoint of their relevance for 21th-century ecosocialism. While there are
some serious limitations in the way both consider the “development of
productive forces,” there are powerful insights in their discussion of the
destructive consequences of capitalist expansion for the environment—an
expansion that generates a disastrous metabolic rift in the exchanges between
human societies and nature. Some ecological Marxists distinguish between “first
stage ecosocialists”—who believe that Marx analyses on ecological issues are
too incomplete and dated to be of real relevance today—and “second stage
ecosocialists,” who emphasize the contemporary methodological significance of Marx’s
ecological critique of capitalism. This paper tries to argue for a third
position (which probably could be accepted by several people of the two groups
above): Marx and Engels’ discussion on ecological issues is incomplete and
dated but despite these shortcomings it does have real relevance and
methodological significance today.
While
mainstream ecology has been dismissive of Marx, serious research in the last
decades has shown that Marx and Engels developed some very important insights
on ecological issues. The pioneers of this research have been James O’Connor
and the journal Capitalism Nature Socialism, but in the recent years, the most
systematic and thorough investigations in this respect has been developed by
John Bellamy Foster and his friends at Monthly Review.
Does this
mean that ecology occupies a central place in the Marxian theoretical
apparatus? I do not think so, but this does not result from any shortcoming;
it simply reflects the fact that the ecological crisis in the 19th century was
just beginning and was far from being as catastrophic as in our days. As I will
try to show below, there are also some problems in Marxian discussion of the
“development of productive forces” and some internal tensions in the
understanding of socialism. Nevertheless, one can find in Marx and Engels’
writings a series of arguments and concepts that are essential to understanding
the connection between capitalism and the destruction of the natural
environment, as well as to define a social-ecological alternative to the
prevailing system.
Let us begin
by discussing certain criticisms addressed by mainstream ecologists against
Marx and Engels:
(1) “The
founders of historical materialism saw human beings as in permanent struggle
with nature. They had a Promethean view of humanity as the master and conqueror
of nature.” Indeed, there are passages in Marx and Engels’ writings which can
be interpreted this way. For instance, when they celebrate the achievements of
the bourgeoisie in the Communist Manifesto (1848), Marx and Engels state:
Subjection of
Nature’s forces to man, machinery, application of chemistry to industry and
agriculture, steam-navigation, railways, electric telegraphs, clearing of whole
continents for cultivation, canalisation of rivers, whole populations conjured
out of the ground—what earlier century had even a presentiment that such
productive forces slumbered in the lap of social labour? (1987, Ch. 1)
Foster
criticizes my use of the term “Prometheanism” for Marx and Engels. I agree that
this is an inadequate generalization, but I cannot follow him in his “non-Promethean”
reading of this specific passage in the Communist Manifesto (2000, 135–140). In
a recent discussion on this passage of the Communist Manifesto, Saito
acknowledges that “Löwy’s reading of Marx’s alleged ‘Prometheanism’ might seem
hard to refute here ... but can hardly be generalized across Marx’s entire
career ... ” (2016). Agreed! Indeed, it would be a serious mistake to conclude
that these lines represent Marx’s general outlook on the issue of humanity’s
relations to the natural world. As Kovel convincingly argues—against Ted
Benton, Rainer Grundmann and others—a close reading of Marx would clearly show
that he was not a Promethean, that is, “an unreconstructed apostle of
Enlightenment in its rankest industrial form” (2007, 231).
What is
striking in Marx’s early writings is his outspoken naturalism, his vision of
the human being as a natural, inseparable from the natural environment. For
instance, here is what Marx stresses in his Manuscripts of 1844: “That man’s
physical and spiritual life is linked to nature means simply that nature is
linked to itself, for man is part of nature.” True, Marx is a humanist thinker,
but he defines communism as a form of humanism that is, “at the same time, an
accomplished naturalism, as well as the genuine solution of the conflict
between man and nature.” Thanks to the positive abolition of private property,
human society will become “the perfected unity in essence of man with nature,
the true resurrection of nature, the realized naturalism of man and the realized
humanism of nature” (Marx 1975, 348–349). These passages do not deal directly
with the ecological issues and the threats to the environment, but the logic of
this sort of naturalism permits an approach of the human/nature relationship
that is not one-sided.
This attitude
is not limited to Marx’s early writings. One can find a very similar naturalist
approach in a well-known writing by Friedrich Engels from 1876 on The Part
Played by Labor in the Transition from Ape to Man. Here, the naturalist stance
becomes the foundation for a radical critique of predatory forms of human
relationships to the environment:
Let us not,
however, flatter ourselves overmuch on account of our human conquest of nature.
For each such conquest takes its revenge on us ... The people who, in
Mesopotamia, Greece, Asia Minor, and elsewhere, destroyed the forests to obtain
cultivable land, never dreamt that they were laying the basis for the present
devastated condition of these countries, by removing along with the forests the
collecting centres and reservoirs of moisture. When, on the southern slopes of
the mountains, the Italians of the Alps used up the pine forests so carefully
cherished on the northern slopes, they had no inkling that by doing so they
were cutting at the roots of the dairy industry of their region ... Thus at
every step, we are reminded that we by no means rule over nature like a
conqueror over a foreign people, like someone standing outside nature—but that
we, with flesh, blood, and brain, belong to nature, and exist in its midst, and
that all our mastery consists in the fact that we have the advantage of all
other beings of being able to know and correctly apply its laws (Engels 1964,
291–292).
For sure,
this passage has a very general character—it does not deal with the capitalist
mode of production but with older civilizations—but it is nevertheless an
ecological argument of an impressive and surprising modernity, both by its
critique of the “conquering” attitude of human societies and, specifically, by
drawing attention to the disasters resulting from deforestation.
(2) According
to many ecologists, “Marx, following David Ricardo, sees human labor as the
origin of all value and all wealth, neglecting the contribution of nature.”
This criticism simply results from a misunderstanding. Marx uses the
labour-value theory to explain the origin of exchange-value, in the framework
of the capitalist system. Nature, however, participates in the constitution of
real wealth, which is not exchange-value, but use-value. This argument is
explicitly presented by Marx in his Critique of the Gotha Programme (1875),
against the ideas of Ferdinand Lassalle and his followers in the German labour
movement:
Labour is not
the source [die Quelle] of all wealth. Nature is as much the source of
use-values [Gebrauchswerte] (which are, after all, the real wealth !) as
labour, which is itself nothing but the expression of a natural force, human
labour force. (Marx 1965, 15)
(3) Many
ecologists accuse Marx and Engels of “productivism.” Is this accusation
justified? No, insofar as nobody denounced as much as Marx the capitalist logic
of production for production’s sake: the accumulation of capital, wealth and
commodities as an aim in itself. The fundamental idea of a socialist economy—in
contrast to its miserable bureaucratic caricatures—is one of producing
use-values, goods which are necessary for the satisfaction of human needs.
Moreover, the main importance of technical progress for Marx was not the
infinite growth of goods (“having”) but the reduction of the labour journey and
the increase of free time (“being”). The opposition between “having” and
“being” is often discussed in the Manuscripts of 1844. In Capital, Vol. III,
Marx emphasizes free time as the foundation of the socialist “Kingdom of
Freedom” (1968, III, 828). As Burkett has perceptively shown, Marx’s emphasis
on communist self-development, on free time for artistic, erotic or
intellectual activities—in contrast to the capitalist obsession with the
consumption of more and more material goods—leads to a decisive reduction of
production pressure on the natural environment (2009, 329).
However, it
is true that one can find in Marx and Engels—and even more in the dominant
Marxist currents that followed—a rather uncritical stance towards the
productive forces created by capital, and a tendency to see in the “development
of productive forces” the main factor of human progress. The “canonical” text
in this respect is the famous Preface to the Contribution to the Critique of
Political Economy (1859), one of Marx’s writings most loaded with a certain
evolutionism, a belief in inevitable historical progress, and an unproblematic
view of the existing productive forces:
At a certain
stage of their development, the material productive forces enter in
contradiction with the existing relations of production ... From being forms of
development of the productive forces, these relations become fetters (Fesseln).
Then opens an epoch of social revolution ... A social formation never disappears
before all productive forces for which it is broad enough are developed ... .
(Marx 1964, 9)
In this
well-known passage, productive forces created by capital appear as “neutral,”
and revolution has only the task of suppressing the relations of production
which have become “fetters,” “shackles,” for a larger (unlimited?) development
of the productive forces. I will discuss this issue below.
The following
passage from the Grundrisse is a good example of the sec- tions of Marx’s work
which bears witness to an uncritical admiration for the “civilizing action” of
capitalist production, and its overcoming of “nature-worship” as well as other
“barriers and prejudices”:
Just as
production founded on capital created universal industriousness on one side ...
so does it create on the other side a system of general exploitation of the
natural and human qualities ... Thus capital creates the bourgeois society, and
the universal appropriation of nature as well as of the social bond itself by
the members of society. Hence the great civilizing action of capital; its
production of a stage of society in comparison to which all earlier ones appear
as mere local developments of humanity and as nature-idolatry. For the first
time, nature becomes purely an object for humankind, purely a matter of
utility; ceases to be recognized as a power for itself; and the theoretical
discovery of its autonomous laws appears merely as a ruse so as to subject it
under human needs, whether as an object of consumption or as a means of
production. In accordance to this tendency, capital drives beyond national
barriers and prejudices, as much as beyond nature worship, as well as all
traditional ... old ways of life. (Marx 1973, 539)1
In contrast
to this celebration of the “universal appropriation of nature” by capital, in
several other writings, and in particular those concerning agriculture in the
three volumes of Capital, one can perceive key elements for a truly ecological
approach, through a radical criticism of the disastrous results of capitalist
productivism. As Foster has shown with great acumen, we can find in Marx’s
writings a theory of the metabolic rift between human societies and nature, as
a consequence of the destructive logic of capital (2000, 155–167). Marx’s
starting point is the work of German chemist and agronomist Justus von Liebig,
to whom he pays homage: “[T]o have developed from the point of view of natural
science the negative, i.e. destructive side of modern agriculture, is one of
Liebig’s immortal merits” (1970, 638).
The
expression Riss des Stoffwechsels, metabolic rift—a break in the material
exchanges between humanity and the environment—appears as well, for instance,
in Chapter 47,“Genesis of the Capitalist Ground Rent,” in Capital Vol. III:
Large landed
property reduces the agricultural population to a constantly falling minimum,
and confronts it with a constantly growing industrial population crowded
together in large cities. It thereby creates conditions which cause an
irreparable break in the coherence of social interchange prescribed by the
natural laws of life. As a result, the vitality of the soil is squandered, and
this prodigality is carried by commerce far beyond the borders of a particular
state (Liebig)...Large-scale industry and large-scale mechanised agriculture
work together. If originally distinguished by the fact that the former lays
waste and destroys principally labour-power, hence the natural force of human
beings, whereas the latter more directly exhausts the natural vitality of the
soil, they join hands in the further course of development in that the
industrial system in the countryside also enervates the labourers, and industry
and commerce on their part supply agriculture with the means for exhausting the
soil. (Marx 1959, 588)
As with most
other examples which we will discuss below, Marx’s attention focuses on
agriculture and the problem of soil exhaustion, but he relates this issue to a
more general principle: the rift in the metabolism—that is, system of material
exchanges (Stoffwechsel) between human societies and the environment—in
contradiction with the “natural laws of life.” It is interesting to note also
two important suggestions, even if they were not developed by Marx: the
cooperation between industry and agriculture in the rift process, and the
extension of the destruction, thanks to international trade, on a global scale.
The issue of
the metabolic rift can be found also in another well-known passage in Capital
Vol. I: the conclusion of the chapter on great industry and agriculture. It is
one of the most important writings of Marx, because it has a dialectical vision
of the contradictions of “progress” and of its destructive consequences for the
natural environment under capitalist rule:
Capitalist
production ... disturbs the metabolic interaction (Stoffwechsel) between man
and the earth, i.e. prevents the return to the soil of its constituent elements
consumed by man in the form of food and clothing; hence it hinders the
operation of the eternal natural conditions for the lasting fertility of the
soil ... All progress in capitalist agriculture is a progress in the art, not
only of robbing the worker, but of robbing the soil; all progress in increasing
fertility of the soil for a given time is a progress toward ruining the more
long- lasting sources of fertility. The more a country, the United States of
North America, for instance, develops itself on the basis of great industry,
the more this process of destruction takes place quickly. Capitalist
production, therefore, only develops the technique and the degree of
combination of the social process of production by simultaneously undermining
the original sources of all wealth—the soil and the worker. (Marx 1970,
637–638)
Several
elements are significant in this important passage:
. (1)
The idea that progress can be destructive, a “progress” in the
degradation and deterioration of the natural environment. The example chosen by
Marx is limited—the loss of fertility by the soil—but it leads him to raise the
larger issue of the attacks on nature, on the “eternal natural conditions,” by
capitalist production.
. (2)
The exploitation and debasement of the workers and of nature are presented
from a similar viewpoint, as result of the same predatory logic, the logic of
capitalist great industry and industrial agriculture. This is a topic that
often appears in Capital (see Foster 2000, 155–157).
The direct
association between the brutal capitalist exploitation of the proletariat and
of the earth lays the theoretical ground for a strategy articulating class
struggle and ecological struggle, in a common fight against the domination of
capital.
Marx (1959, 85) is persuaded that “a rational agriculture is incompatible with the capitalist system ... and needs either the hand of the small farmer living by his own labour or the control of associated producers.” There is a radical opposition between the immediatist logic of capital and the possibility of a “rational” agriculture, based on a much longer temporality and in a sustainable and intergenerational perspective, which respects the natural environment. Marx rejoices that even conservative chemists such as James Johnston recognize that private property is an “insurmountable barrier” for a really rational agriculture.
The reason for this is that:
the whole
spirit of capitalist production, which is directed toward the immediate gain of
money are in contradiction to agriculture, which has to minister to the entire
range of permanent necessities of life required by the chain of successive
generations. (Marx 1959, 477)
A striking
example of this contradiction, according to Marx, is the forests, which are
only managed according to the general interest when they escape private
property and are under public control. The issue of forest destruction is, next
to the exhaustion of soils, the main example of ecological disasters discussed by Marx and Engels. The issue is often discussed in Capital: “agriculture
and industry have been so active (tätig) in the destruction of forests, writes
Marx, that anything that has been done for their conservation is insignificant
in comparison” (Marx 1968, 247). The two phenomena—degradation of forests and
of land—are in fact perceived as directly related. In a passage from Dialectics
of Nature, Engels mentions the destruction of the Cuban forests by the large
Spanish coffee producers and the resulting desertification of the soils as a typical
example of the short-sighted and predatory attitude towards nature of the
“present mode of production,” and its indifference for the long-term harmful
consequences on the natural environment (1964, 185).
If Marx and
Engels have a clear and coherent diagnosis of the destructive dynamics of
capitalism on nature, the way they understood the socialist programme in
relation to the environment is not without internal tensions. On one side, as
we saw above, we have several passages that seem to conceive socialist
production as being simply the collective appropriation of the forces and means
of production developed by capitalism: once suppressed, the “shackles”
represented by the capitalist relations of production—in particular the
property relations—these forces will be able to develop without fetters. There
seems to be here a sort of substantial continuity between the capitalist and
the socialist productive apparatus, the issue for socialism being essentially
the planned and rational collective administration of the material civilization
created by capital. For instance, in the famous conclusion to the chapter on
primitive accumulation in Capital Vol. I, Marx emphasizes:
The monopoly
of capital becomes a fetter (Fessel) for the mode of production which grew and
prospered under it. The socialisation of labour and the centralisation of the
means of production arrived at a point where they cannot any more remain in
their capitalist husk (Hülle). This husk breaks into pieces. The hour of
capitalist property has sound ... Capitalist production engenders its own
negation with the necessity of a natural process. (Marx 1970, 791)
This passage
seems to leave untouched, in a socialist perspective, the whole productive
process created by capitalism, challenging only the “husk” represented by
private property (“monopoly”), which became an obstacle for the economic
progress.
The same type of logic of continuity can be found in certain passages of Engels’ Anti-Dühring, where socialism is perceived as synonymous with the unlimited development of productive forces:
The expansive
force of the means of production breaks the chains (Bande) which the capitalist
mode of production had laid on them. Their liberation from these chains is the
only condition required for an uninterrupted development of the productive
forces, progressing always faster, and therefore, for a practically unlimited
(schrankenlosen) growth of production itself. (Engels 1959, 263)
In this sort
of conception of socialism, there is little room for any concern with the
natural limits of the planet. However, there are several other writings, by
both Marx and Engels, where the ecological dimension of the socialist programme
is taken into account, thus laying the ground for an ecosocialist perspective.
In an interesting passage in Capital Vol. I, Marx suggests that in
pre-capitalist societies, the metabolism between human communities and nature
was assured “spontaneously” (naturwüchsig); in a socialist society (the word
does not appear but its meaning is clarified) the Stoffwechsel with nature will
be re-established in a systematic and rational way (1970, 528). Marx did not
develop this intuition, but it is significant that he saw as the task of
socialism to restore, in a new form, the spontaneous harmony with nature of
pre-capitalist communities with that of a rational and planned one—a very
relevant discussion in the context of indigenous social-ecological struggles in
Latin America today, for example.
In fact, Marx
considered the preservation of natural conditions as an essential task of
socialism. For instance, in Vol. III of Capital, he opposes to the capitalist
logic in agriculture, based on brutal exploitation and exhaustion of the soil,
a different logic, a socialist one, grounded in “the conscious and rational
treatment of the land as permanent communal property”—a treatment that
considers the soil not as the source for short-sighted profit, but as “the
inalienable condition for the existence and reproduction of the chain of human
generations.” A few pages earlier, we find a very significant statement, which
again directly associates the overcoming of private property with
From the
standpoint of a higher economic form of society, private ownership of the globe
by single individuals will appear quite as absurd as private ownership of one
man by another. Even a whole society, a nation, or even all simultaneously
existing societies taken together, are not the owners of the globe. They are
only its possessors, its usufructuaries, and, like boni patres familias, they
must hand it down to succeeding generations in an improved condition. (Marx
1959, 567)
In other
words, Marx takes fully into account what Hans Jonas will call, much later, the
Principle of Responsibility, the obligation of each generation to respect the
natural environment—the condition of existence for future human generations.
Moreover, in
the same Vol. III of Capital Marx does not define socialism as human
“subjugation” or domination over nature but rather as the rational control of
human material exchange with nature. In the sphere of material production, he
writes,
Freedom in this field can only consist in socialised man, the associated producers, rationally regulating their interchange with Nature, bringing it under their common control, instead of being ruled by it as by the blind forces of Nature. (Marx 1959, 593)2
This proposition will be adopted, almost word by word, by Walter Benjamin, one of the first Marxists of the 20th century to raise this sort of questions. In 1928, in his book One Way Street, Benjamin denounced the idea of human domination of nature as “an imperialist doctrine,” and proposed instead a new conception of the technique as “domination of the relationship between humanity and nature” (1972, 147). It would not be difficult to find in Marx and Engels’ writings other examples of a real interest in the issue of the natural environment, even if they lacked a general and systematic reflection on it. In a recent and very interesting article, Saito argues that Marx’s scientific-natural notebooks following 1868 suggest that:
Marx’s
critique of political economy, if completed, would have put a much stronger
emphasis on the disturbance of the ‘metabolic interaction’ (Stoffwechsel)
between humanity and nature as the fundamental contradiction within capitalism.
(2016)
This may be
so, but it means, reversely, that in its existing incomplete state, Marx’s work
does not present the ecological issue as “the fundamental contra- diction.”
Summarizing the discussions on Marx among ecosocialists, Saito asserts that
“first stage ecosocialists” (to use John Bellamy Foster’s categorization)—such
as André Gorz and James O’Connor—believed that Marx’s analyses on ecological
issues “are too incomplete and dated to be of real relevance today.” In
contrast, “second stage ecosocialists”—such as Foster himself and Paul
Burkett—“emphasize the contemporary methodological significance of Marx’s
ecological critique of capitalism” (Saito 2016). I would modestly argue for a
third position (which probably could be accepted by several people in the two
groups above): Marx and Engels’ discussion on ecological issues is incomplete
and dated, but despite these shortcomings, it does have real relevance and
methodological significance today. In other words, 21st- century ecosocialists
cannot satisfy themselves with a 19th-century Marxian ecological heritage, and
need a critical distance towards some of its limitations. But on the other
hand, an ecology able to confront the contemporary challenges cannot exist
without the Marxist critique of political economy and its remarkable analysis
of the destructive logic inherent to the unlimited accumulation of capital. An
ecology which ignores or despises Marx, his theory of value or his critique of
commodity fetishism and reification, is doomed to become nothing more than a
“correction” of the “excesses” of capitalist productivism. Present-day
ecosocialists can build on the more advanced and coherent arguments of Marx and
Engels in order to: (1) achieve a real materialist understanding of the
perverse dynamics of the system; (2) to develop a radical critique of the
capitalist destruction of the environment; and (3) project the perspective of a
socialist society respecting the “inalienable conditions” of life on Earth.
As Naomi
Klein has forcefully argued, climate change “changes everything.” It is a
mortal threat, not for “the planet”—a silly mantra in the media—but for life on
the planet, and in particular human life. The ecological issue—first of all,
but not only, disastrous global warming—is already, and will become
increasingly so, the main challenge for a renewal of Marxist thought in our
times. It requires from Marxists a radical break with the ideology of linear
progress, and with the foundations of the modern capitalist/industrial
civilization. The blind spot which appears in some “canonical” texts from Marx
and Engels is an uncritical view of the productive forces created by
capital—that is, the technical/industrial apparatus of modern capitalism—as if
they were “neutral,” and as if revolutionaries had only to socialize them,
replacing private by collective appropriation, and putting them to function at
the service of the working class.
Ecosocialists
should take their inspiration from Marx’s remarks on the Paris Commune: Workers
cannot take possession of the capitalist state apparatus and put it to work at
their service. They have to “break it” and replace it by a radically different,
democratic and non-statist form of political power. The same applies, mutatis
mutandis, to the productive apparatus, which is not “neutral,” but carries in
its structure the imprint of its development at the service of capital
accumulation and the unlimited expansion of the market. This puts it in
contradiction with the needs of environmental protection and with the health of
the population. One must therefore “revolutionize” it in a process of radical
transformation. Of course, many scientific and technological achievements of
modernity are precious, but the whole productive system must be transformed,
and this can be done only by ecosocialist methods, that is, through the social
appropriation of the main means of production and a democratic planning of the
economy which takes into account the preservation of the ecological
equilibrium. This means first of all the rapid replacement of fossil-fuel
energy—responsible for the catastrophic process of climate change—with
renewable sources of energy (wind, sun, water), but also an end to destructive
agro-industry, a profound change in transport systems, in consumption patterns
etc. In other words, ecosocialism means a radical, i.e. revolutionary, break
with the whole capitalist pattern of civilization. It aims not only at a new
mode of production and a new form of society, but in the last analysis at a new
paradigm of civilization, a new way of life, based on values of freedom,
equality, solidarity, and respect for “Mother Nature.”
Endnotes:
1John Bellamy
Foster (2010, 93–106) has an interesting analysis of the Grundrisse, but I’m
afraid I cannot agree with his interpretation of this specific passage.
2The control
refers to the metabolism (the masculineihm) and not to nature (feminine noun in
German).
References
Benjamin,
Walter. 1972. Einbahnstrasse (1928) Gesammelte Schriften [One Way Street
(1928), Collected Works]. Vol. IV. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag.
Burkett,
Paul. 2009. Ecological Economics. Toward a Red and Green Political Economy.
Chicago, IL: Haymarket Books.
Engels,
Friedrich. 1959. Anti-Dühring. Translated by Emile Burns. Moscow: Progress
Publishers.
Engels,
Friedrich. 1964. Dialectics of Nature. Translated by Clemens Dutt. Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Foster, John
Bellamy. 2000. Marx’s Ecology: Materialism and Nature. New York: Monthly Review
Press.
Foster, John
Bellamy. 2010. “Marx’s Grundrisse and the Ecology of Capitalism.” In The
Ecological Rift, Capitalism’s War on Earth, edited by John Bellamy Foster,
Brett Clark, and Richard York, 93–106. New York, NY: Monthly Review Press.
Kovel, Joel.
2007. The Enemy of Nature. New York, NY: Zed Books.
Marx, Karl,
1959. Capital. Vol. III. Translated by The Institute of Marxism-Leninism,
Moscow. New York, NY: International Publishers.
Marx, Karl.
1964. “Zur Kritik der Politischen Ökonomie, Vorwort” [A Contribution
to the
Critique of Political Economy, Foreword]. In Marx Engels Werke, Vol. 13.Berlin:
Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl.
1965. “Kritik des Gothaer Programms” [Critique of the Gotha Program].
In Marx
Engels Werke, Vol. 19, 15–32. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl.
1968. Das Kapital. Vol. II, Marx Engels Werke, Vol. 24. Berlin: Dietz Verlag.
Marx, Karl.
1970. Capital. Vol. I. Translated by Ben Fawkes. New York, NY: Vintage. Marx,
Karl. 1973. Grundrisse. Translated by Martin Nicolau. New York, NY: Vintage.
Marx, Karl. 1975. Manuscripts of 1844. Translated by Rodney Livingstone. New
York, NY: Vintage.
Marx, Karl,
and Friedrich Engels. 1987. Manifesto of the CommunistParty. https://
www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1848/communist-manifesto/index.htm. Saito,
Kohei. 2016. “Marx’s Ecological Notebooks.” Monthly Review 67 (9).
http://monthlyreview.org/2016/02/01/marxs-ecological-notebooks/.
Dear Sirs, you lay the blame for a poor ecology of the modern world on capitalism, while believing that socialism would be better. But it is a mistake. The latter would be dangerous not only for nature, but for mankind too. See https://socialism-marxism.blogspot.lt/
ReplyDelete